About

The SHARES Project examined an unexplored and largely unrecognised problem: the allocation of international responsibility among multiple states and other actors. It uncovered the nature and extent of the problem of sharing responsibility in an increasingly interdependent and heterogeneous international legal order. The Project produced output, offering new concepts, principles and perspectives for understanding how the international legal order may deal with shared responsibility. SHARES was a research project of the Amsterdam Center for International Law, a leading research center within the University of Amsterdam. It was funded by a European Research Council Advanced Grant of 2.1 million euro, obtained in 2010 by Professor André Nollkaemper. The Project ran until the end of 2015.

Sunday, October 30, 2011

Dublin and Beyond: ‘Each According to Its Abilities’?

 Posted by: 

Refugees are legally and morally entitled to some form of protection. This is generally undisputed. The disagreement begins when we ask the question which state will be called upon to provide that protection? David Miller discusses a comparable question in a situation where a person collapses on the street. In his article Distributing Responsibilities, Miller argues that the collapsed person is more likely to receive assistance if there is a single person, rather than several persons, passing by. This is true for several reasons, the most important of which, according to Miller, is that if there are several persons passing by, there is no clear allocation of responsibility.

In order to avoid this situation in the context of immigration, European states have, over the past two decades, created rules on responsibility allocation culminating in the Dublin II regulation. This regulation, often regarded as the flagship of the Common European Asylum System, has been the topic of heated debate following the ECtHR judgment in the case of M.S.S. v. Greece and Belgium and the ECJ Advocate-General’s opinion in joined cases C-411/10 NS and 493/10 ME. Negotiations on a recast Dublin regulation are ongoing, but seem to be gridlocked. Which lessons can the drafters learn from Miller’s discussion on the distribution of responsibilities?

Currently, the Dublin regulation establishes a hierarchy of criteria for identifying the state responsible for processing an asylum claim. In absence of family connections in the country of asylum, this will usually be the state through which the asylum seeker first entered the European Union. Asylum seekers who move to another state as a secondary movement can be sent back to the state of first entry, thereby increasing pressures on the border states of the European Union. This practice may have severe consequences in terms of human rights, as recognized in the M.S.S. case. Acknowledging that the Dublin system must be improved, the European Commission has proposed to introduce a mechanism for the temporary suspension of transfers to member states where the level of protection falls below Union standards. Unfortunately, given the politically sensitive nature of this ‘emergency mechanism’, member states have to this date been unable to reach agreement on this issue. The other changes proposed mainly relate to an expansion of the family-related allocation criteria and the speeding up of the process of identifying the responsible state. However, reconsideration may be needed beyond these modest changes.

A fundamental recast of the Dublin system should not be concerned with mere changes to the rules on responsibility allocation, ‘but with the underlying principles that should guide us …’, as Miller puts it. According to him, there are four principles (i.e. communitarian principle, causal responsibility principle, moral responsibility principle, capacity principle) that can inform a determination on the assignment of responsibility, three of which can, with some imagination, be recognized in the workings of the Dublin regulation.

A consideration that nowadays dominates the answer to the question which state is responsible for the protection of refugees in the Dublin system, but also in the global refugee regime (i.e. 1951 Convention), is geographic proximity. After all, a geographic proximate country is likely to be the first country of entry and, as such, is likely to have responsibility for many asylum seekers who arrive at its borders. The stated rationale behind this policy is to contain asylum seekers in neighboring countries, since those countries tend to have some sort of special solidarity bonds between them. This connects well to Miller’s communitarian principle. Under that principle, he assumes that agents feel a greater sense of responsibility towards those with whom they share communal ties. However, Miller himself recognizes that this principle cannot be used for all responsibility distributing purposes – a statement that also rings true in the context of immigration. Special solidarity bonds do not always exist between neighboring countries and may even exist between geographically distant countries, making geographic proximity not sufficiently morally justifiable to allocate responsibility in all cases.

Specific to the Dublin system is the idea that responsibility for examining an asylum claim should be allocated to the member state that played the most important part in the entry of the person concerned. This so-called ‘Dublin philosophy’ according to which the responsibility for deciding on an asylum claim is made dependent on the responsibility for controlling the external border, could be said to highlight the causal role played by a particular member state in ‘permitting’ a person to enter the territory of the European Union. As such, it conforms to Miller’s causal responsibility principle. Beyond that, this also involves somewhat of ‘an appraisal of the agent’s conduct’ in policing its land and sea frontiers, leaving the member state in question liable to moral blame for not sufficiently having done so. This corresponds well to Miller’s moral responsibility principle. However, the problem with both the causal and the moral responsibility principle is that they look, in the words of Miller, ‘too exclusively to the past’ in assigning responsibility. Forward-looking considerations, such as effective relief from harm in the future, are therefore not part of a determination on the allocation of responsibility. Such relief is, however, the core focus of refugee protection.

Taking their cue from the previous paragraphs and treating the provision of protection as of overriding concern, the drafters of the amended Dublin regulation may want to consider allocating responsibility on the basis of the fourth principle identified by Miller, the capacity principle. On the basis of this forward-looking principle, responsibility for ending a morally concerning situation should be assigned to the agent that can best bring it to an end. When applied to refugee situations, responsibility would thus fall on the member state that, in view of its absorption capacities, is best placed to offer protection. Besides the fact that the capacity principle, understood in this manner, is likely to be unpopular from a political point of view, it is also complex and problematic in the way that is creates incentives for member states to raise protection standards. Measures to help raise those standards in order to increase the ability of member states to offer protection seem to represent a more feasible interpretation of the capacity principle.

Having said that, the latest proposal by the Polish presidency concerning the introduction of an ‘evaluation mechanism’ should be welcomed. This mechanism, meant as a tool to address protection deficiencies before to grow into full-fledged crises, would be used as a preventive step before triggering the operation of the ‘emergency mechanism’ and will hopefully move negotiations on the Dublin regulation forward.


Tuesday, October 25, 2011

The Responsibility to Protect Temporarily Stranded in Syria

 Posted by: 

On 14 October , High Commissioner for Human Rights Navi Pillay publicly stated that the ‘onus to take protective action’ for the benefit of the Syrian people now lies with the international community. This reference to the international community is a moderate formulation of what seem to be forceful intentions. In concrete terms, the statement can be seen as a call for action by the international community of states under a mandate of the United Nations Security Council (UNSC) based on the responsibility to protect (R2P). Pillay describes the continuing reports of assaults on and killings of civilians by the Syrian government as strong evidence that crimes against humanity are taking place. This is one of the four categories of violations for which operationalization of the R2P is warranted.

The R2P is not yet fully considered to be lex lata. Introduced by the ICISS in 2001, it has been a vehicle for the gradual acceptance of intervention in grave humanitarian crises. Where the notion of humanitarian intervention always remained controversial, the novelty of rephrasing sovereignty to responsibility and adding the focus on prevention and rebuilding seemed to slowly bend the will of the international community of states in favor of concerted action. In 2005, after numerous reports and debates on its shape and content, the concept was accepted in non-binding form in the World Summit Outcome Document. In 2007, pressure by the international community and a mediation process under the skilled leadership of former Secretary-General Kofi Annan helped halt post-election violence in Kenya. Despite it only being labeled as an R2P situation in retrospect, it is still widely seen as a model for implementation of the norm in practice.

Recently, supporters of the R2P have eagerly acclaimed the intervention in Libya as a new sign of the norm’s progressive acceptance. From the start, commentators referred to the crack-down in Libya as a clear-cut case fitting the model of the R2P. However, the precedent set in Libya has become a rather questionable point of reference now that the next crisis calling for operationalization of the R2P is discounted based on a political deadlock in the UNSC. Is this indecision perhaps proof of the fact that the R2P is merely a legal concept justifying politically motivated executive action which would be undertaken regardless?[1] Or is there hope that former Secretary-General Dag Hammarsjköl’s vision of neutral and impartial executive action by the UN will one day be realized? In any case, the hypocrisy of the current situation can hardly be ignored. The UNSC will not easily discard its stigma of acting arbitrarily and being driven by neocolonialism.

It seems that the only manner in which the much needed neutral basis for operationalization of the R2P could be strengthened is reforming the decision making process. A multitude of ideas to this effect, have already been forwarded, one more feasible than the other. An example is imposing an obligation to give reasons for a veto on the permanent members of the UNSC and the possibility of overriding a veto in certain cases.[2] Erecting an independent advisory body to determine when measures based on the R2P should be taken could also be of great added value. However, such drastic acts of reform are unlikely to take place without being inspired by a new grand twist in the history of mankind. It looks like it might take a crisis beyond Syria to bring the R2P back into fashion.


[1]    Orford, Anne, International Authority and the Responsibility to Protect (Cambridge UP, 2011).

[2]    Peters, Anne, ‘The Responsibility to Protect and the Permanent Five – The Obligation to give reasons for a veto’ in Nollkaemper, André and Julia Hoffman (eds), The Responsibility to Protect (awaiting publication, 2011).


The chaos in Libya is also the responsibility of Europe

Posted by: Wester Karin In December 2014, the United Nations reported that in the previous months hundreds of civilians had been killed in t...